The platform will undergo maintenance on Sep 14 at about 7:45 AM EST and will be unavailable for approximately 2 hours.
2014
DOI: 10.1093/mind/fzu072
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Is Evaluative Compositionality a Requirement of Rationality?

Abstract: This paper presents a new solution to the problems for orthodox decision theory posed by the Pasadena game and its relatives. I argue that a key question raised by consideration of these gambles is whether evaluative compositionality (as I term it) is a requirement of rationality: is the value that an ideally rational agent places on a gamble determined by the values that she places on its possible outcomes, together with their mode of composition into the gamble (i.e. the probabilities assigned to them)? The … Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
18
0

Year Published

2015
2015
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
7

Relationship

0
7

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 31 publications
(18 citation statements)
references
References 10 publications
0
18
0
Order By: Relevance
“…We are thus agreeing withSeidenfeld et al (2009) andSmith (2014) in rejecting what Smith (2014: 465) calls 'the principle of compositionality': 'the value which a rational agent places [or at least should place] on a gamble is [solely] a function of the values which she places on the possible outcomes of the gamble, together with the probabilities assigned to those outcomes by the gamble'. W and SP1 assign the same probabilities to the same payoffs but are not equally valuable.…”
mentioning
confidence: 81%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…We are thus agreeing withSeidenfeld et al (2009) andSmith (2014) in rejecting what Smith (2014: 465) calls 'the principle of compositionality': 'the value which a rational agent places [or at least should place] on a gamble is [solely] a function of the values which she places on the possible outcomes of the gamble, together with the probabilities assigned to those outcomes by the gamble'. W and SP1 assign the same probabilities to the same payoffs but are not equally valuable.…”
mentioning
confidence: 81%
“…For additional discussion of Easwaran's approach, seeFine (2008),Sprenger and Heesen (2011) andSmith (2014).4 Actually, only one of us (Vallentyne) finds Finite Weak Expectations compelling. The other(Lauwers) finds it compelling for one-stage lotteries but not for compound lotteries (e.g.…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Likewise, if a stochastically dominates a , then the area of the utility contour corresponding to a will 37. The proposal offered by Smith (2014) yields verdicts in an equally broad range of cases. But, like Hájek (2014), I find many of these verdicts implausible.…”
Section: Stochastic Equivalence and Stochastic Dominancementioning
confidence: 99%
“…So far, discussions of this issue have generally favored the first option. For example, Seidenfeld et al (2009), Smith (2014), and Lauwers and Vallentyne (2016) all suggest we should reject Stochastic Equivalence and Stochastic Dominance, and thus reject views which entail those principles, like Difference Minimizing Theory. I disagree.…”
Section: The Case In Favormentioning
confidence: 99%
“…(...) Restrict decision theory to finite state spaces (...) Restrict decision theory to bounded utility functions." Nicholas J.J. Smith (2014), notably, defends a hybrid of these:…”
Section: Other Responsesmentioning
confidence: 99%