2015
DOI: 10.1002/tht3.185
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Intuitive Dilation?

Abstract: Roger White objects to interval‐valued credence theories because they produce a counterintuitive “dilation” effect in a story he calls the Coin Game. We respond that results in the Coin Game were bound to be counterintuitive anyway, because the story involves an agent who learns a biconditional. Biconditional updates produce surprising results whether the credences involved are ranged or precise, so White's story is no counterexample to ranged credence theories.

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1

Citation Types

0
8
0

Year Published

2017
2017
2022
2022

Publication Types

Select...
4
3

Relationship

0
7

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 11 publications
(8 citation statements)
references
References 18 publications
(23 reference statements)
0
8
0
Order By: Relevance
“…25 A further option would be for both your credence in HEADS and your credence in P to adjust, but this is no more appealing than the alternatives. 26 More about why these options are counterintuitive can be found in White (2010), and responses to many of these arguments can be found in Joyce (2010, Sturgeon 2010, and Hart and Titelbaum 2015. In this paper I do not get into the interesting debate over whether dilation is an acceptable consequence of imprecise probabilism.…”
Section: Dilationmentioning
confidence: 92%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…25 A further option would be for both your credence in HEADS and your credence in P to adjust, but this is no more appealing than the alternatives. 26 More about why these options are counterintuitive can be found in White (2010), and responses to many of these arguments can be found in Joyce (2010, Sturgeon 2010, and Hart and Titelbaum 2015. In this paper I do not get into the interesting debate over whether dilation is an acceptable consequence of imprecise probabilism.…”
Section: Dilationmentioning
confidence: 92%
“…That the agent's credence in HEADS would (intuitively) be unchanged by seeing the coin land P side up holds only because the agent's credence in P is the range (0,1). In scenarios where the agent's credence in P at t 0 is not symmetrical, intuitively the agent's credence in HEADS should change(Joyce 2010;Sturgeon 2010;Hart and Titelbaum 2015). See also footnote 29.28 Similarly, this holds only because the agent is certain that the coin is fair.…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…It remains to be seen as to whether there are genuine grounds for thinking Condition 2 is false. 6 4.2 At the races Hart and Titelbaum (2015) put forward an example, At the Races, which might suggest that rather than implying it, Condition 2 is incompatible with the Principle of Indifference. 7 Suppose your credence that a toss with a fair coin comes up heads is 1 2 , i.e., P (A|XE) = 1 2 where X says that P * (A) = 1 2 and E is admissible.…”
Section: Cars Fins and Antennaementioning
confidence: 99%
“…Indeed, P (A|A ↔ F ) > P (¬A|A ↔ F ) iff P (AF ) > P (¬A¬F ). 7 Strictly speaking, Hart and Titelbaum (2015) object to an argument of Roger White (2010) rather than Condition 2. However, the assumption they attack, i.e., Equation (5) on p.175, is similar to Condition 2. that Speedy wins but there is additional background information E which says that precisely one horse can win.…”
Section: Cars Fins and Antennaementioning
confidence: 99%
“…4 Lastly, one might try to attack C4. One might try to resist the intuition behind C4 on the grounds that conditioning on a biconditional is somewhat counterintuitive (Hart and Titelbaum 2015;Titelbaum and Hart 2018). Whether or not this is so, the question remains as to what one should do in our scenario when one supposes that two propositions have the same truth value.…”
Section: Attack the Conditionsmentioning
confidence: 99%