2018
DOI: 10.1111/phib.12133
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Intending is Believing: A Defense of Strong Cognitivism

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1

Citation Types

0
35
0

Year Published

2019
2019
2021
2021

Publication Types

Select...
8

Relationship

0
8

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 32 publications
(35 citation statements)
references
References 51 publications
0
35
0
Order By: Relevance
“…As we will see, I do not think this means that the ground of my practical knowledge is non-evidential (c.f. Small 2012; Marušić and Schwenkler 2018). Rather, on my account, the knowledge in question is quite literally self-evident, that is, what is known provides evidence for itself.…”
mentioning
confidence: 79%
“…As we will see, I do not think this means that the ground of my practical knowledge is non-evidential (c.f. Small 2012; Marušić and Schwenkler 2018). Rather, on my account, the knowledge in question is quite literally self-evident, that is, what is known provides evidence for itself.…”
mentioning
confidence: 79%
“…I thank an anonymous referee for prompting me to clarify this issue. 25 Perhaps they believe this because they think an intention that p is, in fact, a belief that p. For a view like this see, for example, Setiya (2003Setiya ( , 2008Setiya ( , 2009), Velleman (1989Velleman ( , 2007 and Marusic and Schwenkler (2018). 26 At least not directly, but what I go on to say will suggest why I think this view is false.…”
Section: Intention-belief Consistencymentioning
confidence: 97%
“…But this by itself is no cause for concern-indeed, this seems to be precisely what noncognitivists should say about such cases. 20 For defense of a doxastic condition on intention, see, among others, Grice (1971); Audi (1973); Harman (1976); Davis (1984); Wallace (2001); Marušić and Schwenkler (2018). cannot intend to go to the movies unless she desires to go to the movies.…”
Section: Intentionmentioning
confidence: 99%