The Oxford Handbook of Information Structure 2015
DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199642670.013.012
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Information Structure and Presupposition

Abstract: This article surveys and discusses the core points of contact between notions of information structure and notions of presupposition. Section 1 is devoted to the ‘weak’ presuppositional semantics for focus developed by Mats Rooth, describing its properties with regard to verification and accommodation and showing that it can successfully account for a wide range of phenomena. Section 2 examines the stronger thesis that focus–background structures give rise to existential presuppositions, and finds the countera… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1
1

Citation Types

1
3
1

Year Published

2019
2019
2021
2021

Publication Types

Select...
3
1

Relationship

0
4

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 4 publications
(5 citation statements)
references
References 458 publications
1
3
1
Order By: Relevance
“…(In (80d)-(80e), we take the second argument of hit to be the patient and the third argument the agent; therefore hit(e')(K)(R) corresponds to an However, once we bring distance in between the antecedent utterance and the again utterance, as in (85), mirroring Saebø's (83), the pattern reverses, which is exactly what we expect, given our information-structural explanation. Note that the context requires a repetitive (as opposed to a counterdirectional) reading in both ( 84 The Kutchi Gujarati pattern thus tracks the local licensing of focus-related effects that we also find in English, as discussed by Saebø (2016), indicating that the distribution of pacho is indeed governed by information structure.…”
Section: Early Accesssupporting
confidence: 64%
“…(In (80d)-(80e), we take the second argument of hit to be the patient and the third argument the agent; therefore hit(e')(K)(R) corresponds to an However, once we bring distance in between the antecedent utterance and the again utterance, as in (85), mirroring Saebø's (83), the pattern reverses, which is exactly what we expect, given our information-structural explanation. Note that the context requires a repetitive (as opposed to a counterdirectional) reading in both ( 84 The Kutchi Gujarati pattern thus tracks the local licensing of focus-related effects that we also find in English, as discussed by Saebø (2016), indicating that the distribution of pacho is indeed governed by information structure.…”
Section: Early Accesssupporting
confidence: 64%
“…We propose a new take on the background presupposition semantics of focus (Jackendoff 1972, Geurts & van der Sandt 2004a, expanding the basic idea by combining it with principles of discourse coherence (see also Hobbs 1990, Reese 2007 and by making the background presupposition sensitive to pitch contour. Presuppositional accounts of focus face substantial challenges (Dryer 1996, Rooth 1999, Saebø 2016) and we do not agree with how Geurts & van der Sandt (2004a,b) address these. Our solution to these challenges is elaborated in Section 4.6.…”
Section: Our Semantics For Intonationcontrasting
confidence: 56%
“…So Geurts & van der Sandt (2004a: pp28-30) argue instead for a polarity focus, thereby yielding for both (@30a) and (@30b) the tautological presupposition either nobody likes Michael or somebody does. Saebø (2016) and Büring (2004) argue convincingly that this strategy doesn't work, and we agree. Geurts & van der Sandt (2004a: p29) justify polarity focus for focussed quantifiers as follows.…”
Section: Some Challenges To a Presupposition Approachmentioning
confidence: 52%
See 2 more Smart Citations