2016
DOI: 10.1002/tht3.219
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Indiscernibility Does Not Distinguish Particularity

Abstract: According to the indiscernibility characterization of the distinction between particulars and universals, only and all the former have possible numerically distinct indiscernible intrinsic qualitative duplicates. It is argued here that both the sufficiency and the necessity directions are defective and that indiscernibility thus does not distinguish particularity. Against sufficiency: universals may lack intrinsic qualitative character and thus be trivially indiscernible from one another. Against necessity: pl… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
6
0

Year Published

2018
2018
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
6

Relationship

0
6

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 7 publications
(6 citation statements)
references
References 13 publications
(16 reference statements)
0
6
0
Order By: Relevance
“…In particular, according to classic Armstrong's theory, properties are universals yet possess casual powers, or are even individualized by their abilities to enter causal relationships (see Armstrong 1978, 47-50). Furthermore, even if one accepts that causal powers can be attributed only to particularized instances of properties, a reverse problem is still present, namely that it is not obvious that all particulars have causal powers, because while it is common to treat certain abstract entities, such as numbers (see Melia 2008;Giberman 2016), as particulars, it is debatable that they can enter casual relations. Hence, characteristics such as mindindependence or having causal powers do not seem to be identical to the particularity, rather they are associated with some types of particulars.…”
Section: Generic Particularitymentioning
confidence: 99%
“…In particular, according to classic Armstrong's theory, properties are universals yet possess casual powers, or are even individualized by their abilities to enter causal relationships (see Armstrong 1978, 47-50). Furthermore, even if one accepts that causal powers can be attributed only to particularized instances of properties, a reverse problem is still present, namely that it is not obvious that all particulars have causal powers, because while it is common to treat certain abstract entities, such as numbers (see Melia 2008;Giberman 2016), as particulars, it is debatable that they can enter casual relations. Hence, characteristics such as mindindependence or having causal powers do not seem to be identical to the particularity, rather they are associated with some types of particulars.…”
Section: Generic Particularitymentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Analogously, it can be accepted that in the case of tropes, qualitative sameness does not entail identity without making any commitment to the idea of multiple instantiation. Because of this independence, and the fact that philosophers still debate which of the described approaches is the most accurate (see Giberman, 2016), for the purpose of this article I adopt the following disjunctive characterization of the trope interpretation of visual properties:…”
Section: Tropes and Universalsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…To say that x and y are qualitative duplicates is not to say that x and y share the same intrinsic qualitative properties. 28 28 Daniel Giberman (2016) and Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra (2017) argue that Williams's account of the universal/particular distinction fails. I reply that Williams's account is not essential to the theory of universals that follows.…”
Section: Indispensability Of Abstractnessmentioning
confidence: 99%