2008
DOI: 10.1093/aesthj/aym038
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Immoralism and the Valence Constraint

Abstract: Immoralists hold that in at least some cases, moral flaws in artworks can increase their aesthetic value. They deny what I call the valence constraint: the view that any effect that an artwork's moral value has on its aesthetic merit must have the same valence. The immoralist offers three arguments against the valence constraint. In this paper I argue that these arguments fail, and that this failure reveals something deep and interesting about the relationship between cognitive and moral value. In the final se… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1

Citation Types

0
17
0

Year Published

2012
2012
2022
2022

Publication Types

Select...
7
1

Relationship

0
8

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 11 publications
(17 citation statements)
references
References 6 publications
0
17
0
Order By: Relevance
“…All variants of art moralism endorse the valence constraint (Harold 2008): the claim that a feature's effect on the work's moral value must have the same valence as its effect on the work's aesthetic value, regardless of the magnitude of the effect. The valence constraint accommodates both ethicism and moderate moralism; moderate moralists simply include some effects with zero magnitude.…”
Section: Interaction Between Morality and Aesthetics Of Artmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…All variants of art moralism endorse the valence constraint (Harold 2008): the claim that a feature's effect on the work's moral value must have the same valence as its effect on the work's aesthetic value, regardless of the magnitude of the effect. The valence constraint accommodates both ethicism and moderate moralism; moderate moralists simply include some effects with zero magnitude.…”
Section: Interaction Between Morality and Aesthetics Of Artmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Insofar as our responses are directed at others, albeit often fictional others toward whom we cannot act, a work's intrinsic ethical value may, on some definitions, also be considered more narrowly moral. The Humean conception of a work's intrinsic ethical value is sufficiently broad to be accepted by central and opposing figures in the debate, including Berys Gaut (, 9–10), Noël Carroll (), Matthew Kieran (; ), and Daniel Jacobson (, 347), all of whom emphasize the way works of art prescribe or invite feelings, desires, judgments, or imaginings . It is also sufficiently broad to accommodate Robert Stecker's further distinction between attitudes endorsed and attitudes merely explored by a work, as well as his thought that the kind of attitude being endorsed, or the way in which a certain kind of attitude is explored, can make a difference to a work's ethical value (, 150, 159–61; ).…”
Section: The Invariance Stance In the Art And Ethics Debatementioning
confidence: 99%
“…Following a fair amount of confusion in the current debate, a helpful and potentially comprehensive classification of views has emerged that relies on two motivating questions (Gaut , chap. 3; Jacobson ).…”
Section: The Invariance Stance In the Art And Ethics Debatementioning
confidence: 99%
“…4 In separate articles, James Harold and Robert Stecker have offered several reasons to think that this formulation of the immoralist argument, which is wedded to what we might call a perspectival approach, fails. 5 Yet because this is the way in which immoralists have argued their case, neither Harold nor Stecker have addressed, let alone lodged objections against, other ways of arguing for immoralism. Their arguments do not cut against the approach I advocate here, which argues for immoralism by identifying artistically valuable moral flaws in relevant actions undertaken in a work's creation.…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%