2019
DOI: 10.1007/978-3-030-28619-4_10
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

How Should a Robot Assess Risk? Towards an Axiomatic Theory of Risk in Robotics

Abstract: Endowing robots with the capability of assessing risk and making riskaware decisions is widely considered a key step toward ensuring safety for robots operating under uncertainty. But, how should a robot quantify risk? A natural and common approach is to consider the framework whereby costs are assigned to stochastic outcomes-an assignment captured by a cost random variable. Quantifying risk then corresponds to evaluating a risk metric, i.e., a mapping from the cost random variable to a real number. Yet, the q… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
145
0
1

Year Published

2019
2019
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
5
3

Relationship

2
6

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 155 publications
(151 citation statements)
references
References 36 publications
0
145
0
1
Order By: Relevance
“…Additional examples include semi-deviation measures, comonotonic risk measures, spectral risk, and optimized certainty equivalent; see [37] for further examples. The key point is that polytopic risk measures cover a full gamut of risk assessments, ranging from risk-neutral to worst case.…”
Section: Polytopic Risk Measuresmentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…Additional examples include semi-deviation measures, comonotonic risk measures, spectral risk, and optimized certainty equivalent; see [37] for further examples. The key point is that polytopic risk measures cover a full gamut of risk assessments, ranging from risk-neutral to worst case.…”
Section: Polytopic Risk Measuresmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…. , cardinality U poly,V (p) }, inequality(13)can be be rewritten as Now since Q = Q 0 and R = R 0, we also have the following identity:Then by Lemma C.1, inequalities(37) and(38) are equivalent to the existence of a matrix G that satisfies the following inequality for all l ∈ {1, . .…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…In our risk metric discussion, we follow definitions in [11], [12]. Accordingly, our risk metric falls in the category of risk for sequential decision making with deterministic policies, satisfying time-consistency (see [11], [12] for details). Specifically, we formalize the risk by compounding the failure probability,…”
Section: A Pomdp Problemsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…A4 reflects the intuition that a risk-averse agent should prefer to diversify . We refer the reader to Artzner et al (1999) and Majumdar and Pavone (2017) for a thorough justification of these axioms. In the following, we provide a hallmark example of CRMs, the conditional value-at-risk (CVaR) at level α ( 0 , 1 ] .…”
Section: Problem Formulationmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…The limitations of EU theory in modeling human behavior has prompted substantial work on various alternative theories such as rank-dependent EU (Quiggin, 1982), expected uncertain utility (Gul and Pesendorfer, 2014), dual theory of choice (distortion risk measures) (Yaari, 1987), prospect theory (Barberis, 2013; Kahneman and Tversky, 1979), and many more (see Majumdar and Pavone (2017) for a recent review of the various axiomatic underpinnings of these risk measures). Further, one way to interpret the Ellsberg paradox is that humans are not only risk averse, but are also ambiguity averse : an observation that has sparked an alternative set of literature in decision theory on “ambiguity-averse” modeling; see, e.g., the recent review by Gilboa and Marinacci (2016).…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%