2011
DOI: 10.1007/s13194-011-0029-3
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

How do models give us knowledge? The case of Carnot’s ideal heat engine

Abstract: Abstract:Our concern is in explaining how and why models give us useful knowledge. We argue that if we are to understand how models function in the actual scientific practice the representational approach to models proves either misleading or too minimal. We propose turning from the representational approach to the artefactual, which implies also a new unit of analysis: the activity of modelling. Modelling, we suggest, could be approached as a specific practice in which concrete artefacts, i.e., models, are co… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
70
0
5

Year Published

2014
2014
2022
2022

Publication Types

Select...
4
3

Relationship

3
4

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 66 publications
(75 citation statements)
references
References 43 publications
0
70
0
5
Order By: Relevance
“…Epistemic results (theories, models, laws, concepts) are epistemic tools constructed for epistemic uses such as construction of explanations and predictions, model-building (e.g., mechanistic, mathematical, experimental and synthetic models), creative thinking, problem-solving, computer simulations, and design of experimental equipment (Boon and Knuuttila 2009, Knuuttila and Boon 2011, Boon 2012a, Green 2013). 3.…”
Section: Epistemologymentioning
confidence: 99%
See 2 more Smart Citations
“…Epistemic results (theories, models, laws, concepts) are epistemic tools constructed for epistemic uses such as construction of explanations and predictions, model-building (e.g., mechanistic, mathematical, experimental and synthetic models), creative thinking, problem-solving, computer simulations, and design of experimental equipment (Boon and Knuuttila 2009, Knuuttila and Boon 2011, Boon 2012a, Green 2013). 3.…”
Section: Epistemologymentioning
confidence: 99%
“…How to validate computer models for biomedical applications, for instance, is the topic of this special issue. Knuuttila and Boon (2011) argue that much of the justification of a scientific model takes place when building it (rather than by experimental tests only).…”
Section: Justificationmentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…When allowing models a relative autonomy from theories, we may ignore, for example, some causal factors in order to explore certain others and in doing to render the models Bunrealistic.^Indeed, within philosophy of science, it has been argued that modeling often does not strive for realistic representations of its targets; it suffices that they are representative (Morrison and Morgan 1999). Some argue that this is precisely the aspect of modeling that makes models work and allows them to be conveniently mathematically represented (Humphreys 2004, p. 84-86, 116-124;Knuuttila and Boon 2011;Knuuttila 2011;Koponen 2007). Moreover, this is what allows us to learn from the models (Knuuttila 2011;Knuuttila and Boon 2011).…”
Section: Generative Modeling In Science Educationmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Some argue that this is precisely the aspect of modeling that makes models work and allows them to be conveniently mathematically represented (Humphreys 2004, p. 84-86, 116-124;Knuuttila and Boon 2011;Knuuttila 2011;Koponen 2007). Moreover, this is what allows us to learn from the models (Knuuttila 2011;Knuuttila and Boon 2011). Interestingly, as a consequence, the abstractions may make the results derived from the models intractable.…”
Section: Generative Modeling In Science Educationmentioning
confidence: 99%