2006
DOI: 10.1111/j.1096-0031.2006.00100.x
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

From conviction to anti‐superfluity: old and new justifications of parsimony in phylogenetic inference

Abstract: Traditional justifications of parsimony in phylogenetic inference assume a correspondence between character-state similarity and steps (character transformation events). In addition to similarity, justifying arguments appeal to conviction, descriptive efficiency, ad hoc hypotheses of homoplasy and frequentist probability. Each of these rationales fails in so far as the arguments are incoherent or logically inconsistent with the ontological status of what is assumed and being explained historically. An ideograp… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
2
1

Citation Types

2
139
0
1

Year Published

2006
2006
2020
2020

Publication Types

Select...
7
1

Relationship

3
5

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 76 publications
(142 citation statements)
references
References 63 publications
2
139
0
1
Order By: Relevance
“…Two equally parsimonious explanations may have different CIs and RIs, and explanations with the same CI and RI may have different costs. For details, see Kluge and Grant (2006). (108, 0 R 1), and the origin of toe trembling (Character 115, 0 R 1).…”
Section: General Resultsmentioning
confidence: 99%
See 2 more Smart Citations
“…Two equally parsimonious explanations may have different CIs and RIs, and explanations with the same CI and RI may have different costs. For details, see Kluge and Grant (2006). (108, 0 R 1), and the origin of toe trembling (Character 115, 0 R 1).…”
Section: General Resultsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Operational considerations aside (e.g., tree-space searching capabilities), disagreements between the results of unweighted parsimony analysis and the other methods are due to the increased patristic distance required to accommodate the additional assumptions. Kluge and Grant (2006) reviewed the justifications for parsimonious phylogenetic inference previously considered sufficient, namely, conviction (Hennig, 1966), descriptive efficiency (Farris, 1979), minimization of ad hoc hypotheses of homoplasy (Farris, 1983), and statistical, model-based inference (maximum likelihood, Sober, 1988). Finding significant inconsistencies in all of those justifications, Kluge and Grant (2006) proposed a novel justification for parsimony.…”
Section: Conventions and Abbreviationsmentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…However, since the PAR topology is almost identical to the majority rule consensus tree of the BA (Clade-Bayes, sensu Wheeler and Pickett, 2008), the criterion chosen has little implication on the overall phylogenetic hypothesis presented herein. Arguments for the use of parsimony were given and discussed extensively in Farris (1983), Goloboff (2003), and Kluge and Grant (2006). Separate and combined analyses of morphology and molecular data were performed to determine the phylogenetic placement of Marinussaurus curupira among major clades of Gymnophthalminae.…”
Section: Phylogenetic Analysesmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…On the basis of the arguments of Padial et al (2014), we employed tree-alignment (e.g., Sankoff, 1975;Wheeler, 1996;Wheeler, 2012, 2013) in POY 4.1.3 (Varón et al, 2010), which tests hypotheses of nucleotide homology dynamically by optimizing unaligned DNA sequences directly onto alternative topologies (Kluge and Grant, 2006;Wheeler et al, 2006;Grant and Kluge, 2009) while simultaneously optimizing prealigned transformation series as standard static matrices.…”
Section: Phylogenetic Analysesmentioning
confidence: 99%