2014
DOI: 10.1163/18773109-00601002
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

‘Free’ Enrichment and the Nature of Pragmatic Constraints

Abstract: The contextualist approach to utterance interpretation posits processes of “free” pragmatic enrichment that supply unarticulated constituents of the explicit content of utterances. While this proposal is faithful to our intuitions about the truth conditions of utterances, and accommodates the optionality of these pragmatic effects, there remains a doubt about whether contextualism can account in any principled way for what pragmatically derived material enters into explicit content, and what does not. This gap… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
8
0

Year Published

2014
2014
2020
2020

Publication Types

Select...
5
4
1

Relationship

1
9

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 17 publications
(8 citation statements)
references
References 19 publications
0
8
0
Order By: Relevance
“…Stanley's question, then, is what prevents that same pragmatic process from supplying the constituent [OR DUTCHMAN] so that the utterance is predicted (wrongly) to communicate the proposition in (18c) in a context in which it would be relevant. Similarly, free enrichment should enable, he says, an utterance of the sentence in (19a), in a context in which it is common ground that John likes his mother, to communicate the explicature in (19b), which, however, it clearly does not: (18) This overgeneration objection is potentially serious and it has been addressed in some detail by Hall (2008aHall ( , 2008bHall ( , 2009, who sets out to show that a relevancetheoretic account of free pragmatic enrichment would not make the alleged predictions. We cannot review the arguments here (though the distinction we make in section 5.2. between local and global processes is relevant to the issue), but what emerges clearly from Hall's discussion is that when proper attention is given to the nature of the principles and processes at work in pragmatics, 'free' enrichment is in fact quite tightly constrained.…”
Section: (16) Why Does It Rain? It Rains Because Water Vapour In the mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Stanley's question, then, is what prevents that same pragmatic process from supplying the constituent [OR DUTCHMAN] so that the utterance is predicted (wrongly) to communicate the proposition in (18c) in a context in which it would be relevant. Similarly, free enrichment should enable, he says, an utterance of the sentence in (19a), in a context in which it is common ground that John likes his mother, to communicate the explicature in (19b), which, however, it clearly does not: (18) This overgeneration objection is potentially serious and it has been addressed in some detail by Hall (2008aHall ( , 2008bHall ( , 2009, who sets out to show that a relevancetheoretic account of free pragmatic enrichment would not make the alleged predictions. We cannot review the arguments here (though the distinction we make in section 5.2. between local and global processes is relevant to the issue), but what emerges clearly from Hall's discussion is that when proper attention is given to the nature of the principles and processes at work in pragmatics, 'free' enrichment is in fact quite tightly constrained.…”
Section: (16) Why Does It Rain? It Rains Because Water Vapour In the mentioning
confidence: 99%
“… For detailed arguments in favour of this position, see Sperber and Wilson (1986/1995), Carston (1988, 2002), Recanati (2010), and Hall (2014). The opposition case is put by Borg (2004) and Devitt (2013a, 2013b, 2020), among others. …”
mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…There is also lively debate within pragmatics which treats and extends the previous issues: for instance, "what is said" vs. explicature, associative vs. inferential method, primary and secondary pragmatic processes, topdown vs. bottom-up processes, explicature vs. impliciture, ad hoc concepts construction, mutual adjustment, backward/forward inference, meta-representations in communication, radical vs. moderate contextualism, etc. Wilson, 1986, 2002;Levinson, 2000;Bezuidenhout, 2002;Recanati, 2007Recanati, , 2010Recanati, , 2012Carston, 2002Carston, , 2007Carston, , 2009Wilson and Carston, 2007;Bach, 2010;Mazzone, 2011;Wilson and Sperber, 2012;Carston and Hall, 2012;Belleri, 2013;Hall, 2014). This article will pay especial attention to the truth-conditional pragmatics of Recanati (2010) and the inferential approach to communication of Sperber and Wilson's (2012) relevance theory.…”
Section: What Is Saidmentioning
confidence: 99%