2015
DOI: 10.3765/salt.v0i20.2555
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Focus on reflexive anaphors

Abstract: Focus related phenomena have long been used to draw conclusions about the syntax and semantics of anaphora. I use examples in which focus is the result of information-structural considerations to argue for a semantics of reflexive anaphors. I show that a theory that treats reflexive anaphors as reflexivizing functions is empirically superior to theories that interpret them like variables. The discussion also leads to some interesting conclusions about focus theory. It is argued that the domain of application o… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
5
0

Year Published

2015
2015
2017
2017

Publication Types

Select...
3

Relationship

1
2

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 3 publications
(5 citation statements)
references
References 4 publications
0
5
0
Order By: Relevance
“…26 Unfortunately the facts are not as simple as one might expect. Certain presuppositions, especially those triggered by phi-features, seem to not project universally through only (Spathas 2010;Jacobson 2012;Sudo 2012;Sauerland 2013). For instance, the uniqueness presupposition of the singular definite in (i) does not.…”
Section: Onlymentioning
confidence: 97%
“…26 Unfortunately the facts are not as simple as one might expect. Certain presuppositions, especially those triggered by phi-features, seem to not project universally through only (Spathas 2010;Jacobson 2012;Sudo 2012;Sauerland 2013). For instance, the uniqueness presupposition of the singular definite in (i) does not.…”
Section: Onlymentioning
confidence: 97%
“…Although I need to abstain from detailed discussion of such sentences in this paper, I would like to mention that recent studies such as Cable (2005), Spathas (2010), Jacobson (2012), Sauerland (2013), and Sudo (2012) demonstrate that these sentences are amenable to alternative accounts that do not postulate minimal pronouns and Feature Transmission (see also Maier 2009). Together with the proposals of the present paper, therefore, these theories might provide us with a different, semantically more transparent way of looking at the semantics of phi-features than the Minimal Pronoun Account.…”
Section: Conclusion and Further Prospectsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…As discussed in section 2.1, QA-pairs are subject to the Focus Principle, which is satisfied in (39) and (40) if reflexive anaphors are arity reducers, as suggested in (4a) (Spathas 2010(Spathas , 2011 Given exhaustification, the answer in both (39) and (40), which denotes the proposition that Zelda praised Zelda is a complete answer. In the case of (39), the answer determines that it is true that Zelda praised Zelda and false that Oscar praised Zelda and Lucie praised Zelda.…”
Section: Subject Alternatives and The Question Rulementioning
confidence: 99%
“…Roberts 1996Roberts , 2004 My argument is based on the distribution of the alternatives generated by narrow focus on reflexive anaphors in English. Spathas (2010Spathas ( , 2011 observes that narrow focus on a reflexive anaphor is licensed in two rather different environments (see also Ahn 2012). For example, in the Question-Answer (QA) pairs in (2) and (3), the same sentence with the same intonational contour is used to answer both an object wh-question as in (2), as well as a subject wh-question as in (3).…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation