Epistemic Reasons, Norms and Goals 2016
DOI: 10.1515/9783110496765-012
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Epistemic Normativity: From Direct to Indirect Epistemic Consequentialism

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...

Citation Types

0
2
0

Year Published

2017
2017
2023
2023

Publication Types

Select...
2
2
2

Relationship

1
5

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 16 publications
(2 citation statements)
references
References 0 publications
0
2
0
Order By: Relevance
“…We can run versions of this case in which the agent is assured that p will be output by the process ahead of their decision to adopt B, and others where they are unaware. In neither version would the fairy's offer redeem believing p in such a way.13 This is notGoldman (1979)'s process reliabilism (seeGoldman, 2015, (a reply to Berker) and discussion inBerker, 2015 andVahid, 2016). Process reliabilism doesn't make conduciveness sufficient for justification.…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…We can run versions of this case in which the agent is assured that p will be output by the process ahead of their decision to adopt B, and others where they are unaware. In neither version would the fairy's offer redeem believing p in such a way.13 This is notGoldman (1979)'s process reliabilism (seeGoldman, 2015, (a reply to Berker) and discussion inBerker, 2015 andVahid, 2016). Process reliabilism doesn't make conduciveness sufficient for justification.…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…There are lots of examples in the relevant literature that can bring out this point. See, for example, Vahid ().…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%