2009
DOI: 10.1007/s11217-009-9165-z
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Emotion Education without Ontological Commitment?

Abstract: Emotion education is enjoying new-found popularity. This paper explores the 'cosy consensus' that seems to have developed in education circles, according to which approaches to emotion education are immune from metaethical considerations such as contrasting rationalist and sentimentalist views about the moral ontology of emotions. I spell out five common assumptions of recent approaches to emotion education and explore their potential compatibility with four paradigmatic moral ontologies. I argue that three of… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
10
0

Year Published

2011
2011
2016
2016

Publication Types

Select...
5
2
1

Relationship

2
6

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 18 publications
(10 citation statements)
references
References 15 publications
0
10
0
Order By: Relevance
“…Emotion also has a more general epistemic role in Aristotle’s virtue theory as it provides the overarching intellectual virtue of phronêsis – which oversees, integrates and adjudicates the whole virtue repertoire – with the required sensitivity to, and proper perception of, morally relevant features of the circumstances at hand (see Roberts 2013, 201). Although emotion does not create moral value from scratch – this is not a sentimentalist account but a soft rationalist and a soft realist one (Kristjánsson 2010a, 2010b) – the assumption is that without emotions, the moral enterprise would never have gotten off the ground in the first place as we would not have learned how to track the morally relevant features of situations.…”
Section: Aristotle On the Desert-based Emotionsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Emotion also has a more general epistemic role in Aristotle’s virtue theory as it provides the overarching intellectual virtue of phronêsis – which oversees, integrates and adjudicates the whole virtue repertoire – with the required sensitivity to, and proper perception of, morally relevant features of the circumstances at hand (see Roberts 2013, 201). Although emotion does not create moral value from scratch – this is not a sentimentalist account but a soft rationalist and a soft realist one (Kristjánsson 2010a, 2010b) – the assumption is that without emotions, the moral enterprise would never have gotten off the ground in the first place as we would not have learned how to track the morally relevant features of situations.…”
Section: Aristotle On the Desert-based Emotionsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Education of the emotions has, of course, become a buzzword in many recent approaches to moral emotion. Aristotelianism offers the additional bonus of supplying those approaches with an ontology of ‘soft rationalism’ that makes full sense of the role and salience of emotions, without buying into unsavoury forms of sentimentalism about emotions as arational and independent creators of moral value (Kristjánsson, 2010b).…”
Section: The Pros Of Aristotelianismmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…They all consider ontology extremely important to philosophy and also to practice of education, up to suggesting exactly the phrase "ontological turn" in their texts or even titles (Barnett, 2004;2009;Dall'Alba & Barnacle, 2007;Pio & Varkøy, 2012;Rømer, 2013). Common themes in these papers are: values and aims of education (Ibid, Bonnett, 2000;Brook, 2012;Kristjánsson, 2010), ontological commitments of educational research (Wegerif, 2008), and especially the concept of dialogue and its ontological bearings in education ( , 2012;Wegerif, 2008). A very strong shared influence is from Heideggerian phenomenological and existential ontology of human existence, being-in-the-world (Dall'Alba & Barnacle, 2007;Pio & Varkøy, 2012).…”
Section: An Ontological Turn In the Philosophy Of Education -Ontologimentioning
confidence: 99%