2017
DOI: 10.1088/1367-2630/aa9168
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Deriving robust noncontextuality inequalities from algebraic proofs of the Kochen–Specker theorem: the Peres–Mermin square

Abstract: When a measurement is compatible with each of two other measurements that are incompatible with one another, these define distinct contexts for the given measurement. The Kochen-Specker theorem rules out models of quantum theory that satisfy a particular assumption of context-independence: that sharp measurements are assigned outcomes both deterministically and independently of their context. This notion of noncontextuality is not suited to a direct experimental test because realistic measurements always have … Show more

Help me understand this report
View preprint versions

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1

Citation Types

1
47
0

Year Published

2018
2018
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
7

Relationship

1
6

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 30 publications
(48 citation statements)
references
References 48 publications
1
47
0
Order By: Relevance
“…As such, it is important to understand where the operational equivalences come from in the first place. Historically, most operational equivalences for generalized noncontextuality have originated in quantum no-go theorems for noncontextuality [7,8,13,14,25,26], or in a frustrated network that can be used to build a quantum no-go theorem [27,28].…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…As such, it is important to understand where the operational equivalences come from in the first place. Historically, most operational equivalences for generalized noncontextuality have originated in quantum no-go theorems for noncontextuality [7,8,13,14,25,26], or in a frustrated network that can be used to build a quantum no-go theorem [27,28].…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…hence there exists an odd k = 9 (with n k = n 9 = 3 > 0) such that 3 j=1 p(w (9) j ) = 1, an odd number. Since |F | = 118 is even, we have a KS contradiction for this hypergraph from Lemma 6.…”
Section: The Kochen-specker (1967) Constructionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…8 Now consider an induced subscenario of 2Reg(G(K m,n \K 1,k )) or 2Reg(G(K m,n \K k,1 )) that consists entirely of singletons so that the number of hyperedges in 2Reg(G(K m,n \K 1,k )) or 2Reg(G(K m,n \K k,1 )) is twice the number of singletons in this induced subscenario. 9 Extending this induced subscenario by adding a k-hypercycle (disjoint from the subscenario) leads to an induced subscenario of 2Reg(K m,n ), namely, one that is a union of a k-hypercycle with the singletons. (See Fig.…”
Section: Contextuality Scenarios and Extremal Probabilistic Models Onmentioning
confidence: 99%
See 2 more Smart Citations