2011
DOI: 10.1111/j.1365-2753.2011.01750.x
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Criticizing the data: some concerns about empirical approaches to ethics

Abstract: There are strong arguments in favour of the need for more 'empirically informed philosophy'. Using papers in the current issue of JECP as case studies, I raise fundamental and unresolved methodological questions about the proper relationship between philosophy and empirical research, in particular concerning the relationship between 'data' in empirical research and the 'responses' people give in to questions in the process of philosophical dialogue. There are tensions between the role of data in empirical rese… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1

Citation Types

0
19
0

Year Published

2011
2011
2019
2019

Publication Types

Select...
6

Relationship

2
4

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 8 publications
(19 citation statements)
references
References 22 publications
0
19
0
Order By: Relevance
“…The ‘empirical turn’ is characterized by the notion that it possesses a distinctive difference from descriptive ethics because it seeks to develop normative understanding through its ‘real world’ questioning. In a recent commentary on our article, in which we described and discussed work we had undertaken that might be understood as an example of the ‘empirical turn’, Michael Loughlin seems to have no difficulty in principle with philosophy that is informed by empirical contexts . He writes:
‘The sort of “applied philosophy” that is done in ignorance of, or with indifference to, everyday experience, and in particular that which ignores the social facts that delimit the options and shape the environments of decision makers, is typically of no use to anyone.
…”
Section: The ‘Empirical Turn’ In Bioethics and Loughlin's Dilemmamentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…The ‘empirical turn’ is characterized by the notion that it possesses a distinctive difference from descriptive ethics because it seeks to develop normative understanding through its ‘real world’ questioning. In a recent commentary on our article, in which we described and discussed work we had undertaken that might be understood as an example of the ‘empirical turn’, Michael Loughlin seems to have no difficulty in principle with philosophy that is informed by empirical contexts . He writes:
‘The sort of “applied philosophy” that is done in ignorance of, or with indifference to, everyday experience, and in particular that which ignores the social facts that delimit the options and shape the environments of decision makers, is typically of no use to anyone.
…”
Section: The ‘Empirical Turn’ In Bioethics and Loughlin's Dilemmamentioning
confidence: 99%
“…… Empirically informed philosophy seems, then, to be quite obviously preferable to the empirically uninformed or misinformed variety. …’ (: p. 970).…”
Section: The ‘Empirical Turn’ In Bioethics and Loughlin's Dilemmamentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Arguably, the sciences seek to give us adequate descriptions of the world 2 – and the term ‘sciences’ here includes social sciences and psychology, which seek to give us descriptions of the social world and the human psyche. Philosophical enquiry is, in contrast, typically normative in nature [48], addressing in a very immediate way questions phrased most appropriately in the first person: what should I/we think about issue X? The question of what people in a given time or place do, as a matter of fact, think is part of the subject matter of psychology, but no amount of knowledge about this question can tell us what we should think about the matter.…”
Section: Empirical Philosophy? Research Evidence Epistemology and Etmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…In 2010, the journal presented its first ever philosophy thematic edition, including papers by some of the most original and incisive thinkers the discipline has to offer on a vast range of subjects of urgent practical import [11]. This, the second thematic edition of the Journal of Evaluation in Clinical Practice to focus specifically on the application of philosophical methods and argumentation to medicine and health care, provides an even greater range of papers [25–60] on the themes of progress in medicine, virtue in practice, and evidence and methodology in research and evaluation. Articles bring fresh and challenging analyses of the relationship between progress in the science and the practice of medicine, the role and limitations of statistical reasoning in medical research, patient involvement, autonomy and rationality, the relationship between reason and emotional engagement in the life of the good practitioner, the role and value of uncertainty in health care and how to promote virtue in practice.…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…The assumption that philosophy, especially in certain fields such as ethics, must be "empirically informed" is not in fact controversial advice (LOUGHLIN 2011). But this is different with the emergent field of X-Phi, or experimental philosophy (EP) (LACKMAN 2006;KNOBE 2004;KNOBE & NICHOLS 2008;APPIAH 2007APPIAH , 2010.…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%