2017
DOI: 10.1098/rsfs.2016.0125
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Convergent? Minds? Some questions about mental evolution

Abstract: ABSTRACT:In investigating convergent minds, we need to be sure that the things we are looking at are both minds and convergent. In determining whether a shared character state represents a convergence between two organisms, we must know the wider distribution and primitive state of that character so that we can map that character and its state transitions onto a phylogenetic tree. When we do this, some apparently primitive shared traits may prove to represent convergent losses of cognitive capacities. To avoid… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
3
0

Year Published

2017
2017
2022
2022

Publication Types

Select...
4
1

Relationship

0
5

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 5 publications
(3 citation statements)
references
References 96 publications
0
3
0
Order By: Relevance
“…The mainstream view (e.g., Morgan’s Canon) is that it’s too easy to fall into a trap of “anthropomorphizing” systems with only apparent cognitive powers, when one should only be looking for models focused on mechanistic, lower levels of description that eschew any kind of teleology or mental capacity ( Morgan, 1903 ; Epstein, 1984 ). However, analysis shows that this view provides no useful parsimony ( Cartmill, 2017 ). The rich history of debates on reductionism and mechanism needs to be complemented with an empirical, engineering approach that is not inappropriately slanted in one direction on this continuum.…”
Section: Technological Approach To Mind Everywhere: a Proposal For A ...mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…The mainstream view (e.g., Morgan’s Canon) is that it’s too easy to fall into a trap of “anthropomorphizing” systems with only apparent cognitive powers, when one should only be looking for models focused on mechanistic, lower levels of description that eschew any kind of teleology or mental capacity ( Morgan, 1903 ; Epstein, 1984 ). However, analysis shows that this view provides no useful parsimony ( Cartmill, 2017 ). The rich history of debates on reductionism and mechanism needs to be complemented with an empirical, engineering approach that is not inappropriately slanted in one direction on this continuum.…”
Section: Technological Approach To Mind Everywhere: a Proposal For A ...mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…about the relation between neuroanatomy and cognition). For example, Cartmill [43] argues that behavioural convergence need not be evidence of cognitive convergence for animals whose neurophysiology is unlikely to sustain intentionality and consciousness-two features of mind that he takes to be of particular interest in the quest to discover cases of convergent cognition. Thus, the tiny brains (in terms of total number of neurons) of jumping spiders rule them out as plausible contenders of cognitive convergence even though, as Cartmill notes, their predatory behaviour, which involves alternating among attack strategies such as stalking, ambushing, and frontal attacks, is as flexible as those of large cats.…”
Section: Rsfsroyalsocietypublishingorg Interface Focus 7: 20170029mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…In their phenomenological approach, the authors conclude that modern neurosciences only give access to “fragments of experience, to blurred and perhaps false images of processes, to the distant shadows of the mind” [ 56 ]. Today, several ways of conceptualising the brain coexist more or less peacefully depending on whether one is in the camp of neurosciences [ 57 , 58 ], evolutionary biology [ 59 , 60 ], physiology, psychoanalysis [ 6 ], network science [ 61 ], physics [ 62 , 63 ], mathematics [ 64 ] or astrophysics [ 65 ]. “What is a brain?” would remain without a coherent answer for a long time to come, since the concept of the brain is so impalpable, and perhaps just as impalpable as the notion of the “ psychès ” and life.…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%