2015
DOI: 10.15173/jhap.v3i8.42
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Conventionalism and the Impoverishment of the Space of Reasons: Carnap, Quine and Sellars

Abstract: This article examines how Quine and Sellars develop informatively contrasting responses to a fundamental tension in Carnap’s semantics ca. 1950. Quine’s philosophy could well be styled ‘Essays in Radical Empiricism’; his assay of radical empiricism is invaluable for what it reveals about the inherent limits of empiricism. Careful examination shows that Quine’s criticism of Carnap’s semantics in ‘Two Dogmas of Empiricism’ fails, that at its core Quine’s semantics is for two key reasons incoherent and that his h… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1

Citation Types

0
3
0

Year Published

2015
2015
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
5

Relationship

0
5

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 6 publications
(4 citation statements)
references
References 79 publications
0
3
0
Order By: Relevance
“…The history of the development of this idea during the middle of the last century is not well understood, but Sellars' reading of Carnap, and more generally the readings of the American philosophers at Iowa in the 1940's, look problematic when considered alongside certain plausible reconstructions of Carnap's project (cf. Carus, 2003 andOlen, 2017;Westphal, 2015 offers a contrastive reading of the Carnapian strands in Quine and Sellars, and a criticism of Quine's extensionalist ambitions). At the same time it is clear that the definitive statement of this period of 20th century philosophy has yet to be written.…”
Section: Some Remarks On Logic and The History Of Philosophymentioning
confidence: 99%
“…The history of the development of this idea during the middle of the last century is not well understood, but Sellars' reading of Carnap, and more generally the readings of the American philosophers at Iowa in the 1940's, look problematic when considered alongside certain plausible reconstructions of Carnap's project (cf. Carus, 2003 andOlen, 2017;Westphal, 2015 offers a contrastive reading of the Carnapian strands in Quine and Sellars, and a criticism of Quine's extensionalist ambitions). At the same time it is clear that the definitive statement of this period of 20th century philosophy has yet to be written.…”
Section: Some Remarks On Logic and The History Of Philosophymentioning
confidence: 99%
“…topics that are somehow related to them but are irrelevant for our purposes, such as those of the synthetic a priori, the ontology of abstract entities and our talk about them, and the myth of the given. The connection between Sellars's view of analyticity and his views on these topics has already been explored in Brandt (2017), Rosenberg (2007, ch. 2), and Westphal (2015). These studies make clear the broader implications Sellars's account of analyticity and his response to Quine might have, but they do not examine them in detail on their own nor his dynamic picture of language behind them.…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Although the present analysis contradicts several centuries of empiricism, I respectfully submit that Kant understood the implications of Hume's Treatise better than Hume's empiricist successors. For example, at its core, Quine's semantics is incoherent, for reasons revealed by his superficial mis‐reading of Hume, ‘Of Scepticism with regard to the senses’ ( Treatise 1.4.2); see Westphal (, ). Kant's epistemology itself, of course, is not an object of empirical knowledge.…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%