1996
DOI: 10.1017/s0008423900014463
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Contending Interpretations of Bentham's Utilitarianism

Abstract: This article illustrates the contours of the continuing debate over Bentham's utilitarianism through an analysis of the secondary literature. It assesses the persuasiveness of the principal contemporary “authoritarian” (despotic, totalitarian, collectivism behaviouralist, constructivist, panopticist and paternalist) and “individualist” (facilitative and liberal) interpretations of Bentham's thought, indicating where they are consistent with his writings and where they are not. Distinctions and conflicts betwee… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
4
0

Year Published

1999
1999
2023
2023

Publication Types

Select...
5
4

Relationship

1
8

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 13 publications
(5 citation statements)
references
References 27 publications
0
4
0
Order By: Relevance
“…Bentham's theory focuses on expediency (Crimmins, 1996). The theory of utilitarianism is rational because it always demands that every existing regulation must be accounted for based on its benefits for as many people as possible, otherwise a regulation that does not have benefits for as many people should be eliminated (Brink, 1986).…”
Section: The Current Concept Of a Notary Civil Guildmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Bentham's theory focuses on expediency (Crimmins, 1996). The theory of utilitarianism is rational because it always demands that every existing regulation must be accounted for based on its benefits for as many people as possible, otherwise a regulation that does not have benefits for as many people should be eliminated (Brink, 1986).…”
Section: The Current Concept Of a Notary Civil Guildmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…This will be repeated in a slightly different format in Politique Naturelle (1773), where Holbach claims that whatever the form of government, it ‘will be good when it will bring happiness to the greatest number’ (d’Holbach [1773a] 2001: 382). This reference to the greatest number formula, however, never translates itself into a rational calculation of interests (Crimmins, 1996: 754). This is primarily because it is not rationality that grounds our interests in Holbach’s thought, but our self-love coupled with our natural sociability.…”
Section: Holbach’s Utilitarian Ethicsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…This said, and as Frey and Stutzer correctly point out, the problems inherent with an analysis based on an aggregate welfare function remain. From a historical point of view, on the other hand, it is awkward for those who believe they are following Bentham that Bentham's utilitarianism has been subject to differing interpretations (see, for example, Crimmins 1996). At the same time, the ambiguity involved in the ‘greatest happiness of the greatest number’ principle, which Bentham himself came to realize late in his life, also makes it hard to pinpoint Bentham on a precise measure of ‘utilitarianism’ as a guide to policy (Goldworth 1969; see also Bentham's cryptic ‘Article on Utilitarianism’, originally dating from 1829, and re‐edited in Bentham 1983b).…”
Section: Final Commentsmentioning
confidence: 99%