2012
DOI: 10.1002/ejsp.1862
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Construing counterfactual worlds: The role of abstraction

Abstract: The present article conceptualizes mental time travel as a special case of transcending psychological distance, which rests on the uniquely human ability to consider counterfactual and hypothetical worlds. We discuss the possible challenges that counterfactuality and futurity present before our cognitive system, which include severing the real from imagined worlds and dealing with uncertainty. We suggest, similar to extant approaches to theory of mind, that the use of abstract–symbolic mental representations h… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
2
1

Citation Types

2
14
0

Year Published

2013
2013
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
6

Relationship

2
4

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 11 publications
(16 citation statements)
references
References 53 publications
2
14
0
Order By: Relevance
“…However, when these actions were negated (e.g., "do not push the button"), motor activation decreased. Negated events, like future ones, describe non-factual world-states and thus should not call upon the same sensory-motor systems with which we encounter reality (Gilead et al, 2012). The present results join this previous work (e.g., Tettamanti et al, 2008;Tomasino et al, 2010) in suggesting that the invocation of concrete/embodied representations is not mandatory, as initially suggested (Hauk et al, 2004), but rather that it is part of a more intricate process by which meaning is construed.…”
Section: Modulation Of Concreteness-related Activity By Tensesupporting
confidence: 85%
See 3 more Smart Citations
“…However, when these actions were negated (e.g., "do not push the button"), motor activation decreased. Negated events, like future ones, describe non-factual world-states and thus should not call upon the same sensory-motor systems with which we encounter reality (Gilead et al, 2012). The present results join this previous work (e.g., Tettamanti et al, 2008;Tomasino et al, 2010) in suggesting that the invocation of concrete/embodied representations is not mandatory, as initially suggested (Hauk et al, 2004), but rather that it is part of a more intricate process by which meaning is construed.…”
Section: Modulation Of Concreteness-related Activity By Tensesupporting
confidence: 85%
“…4 Despite the similarities between past-and future-thought, it is self-evident that they are not one of the same. It is an absolute necessity for cognitive agents to sharply distinguish between factual (past and present) and hypothetical (future) events (Gilead et al, 2012). It appears that due to the grave importance of this distinction, the factual/hypoethical (or realis/irrealis) dimension permeates the inner-substrates of our language (Pinker, 2007) and as the current study shows, is reflected in the way our brains process meaning.…”
Section: Similarities and Differences Between Past And Futurementioning
confidence: 69%
See 2 more Smart Citations
“…In a similar vein, we do not propose that all concepts are necessarily simulated or that all representations require the same amount of simulation. A number of recent theoretical proposals emphasize the need for multiple representational systems, including both embodied and “dis‐embodied” (i.e., abstract) concepts (e.g., Barsalou, ; Dove, ; Gilead, Liberman, & Maril, ; Louwerse & Connell, ; Markman & Brendl, ; Wilson, ). The question of what abstraction is with regard to simulation is very important; here, however, we simply follow the working hypothesis that the required degree of simulation can be viewed as inversely related to the required degree of abstraction: A more automated and engrained representation requires less and/or more shallow simulation for adequate retrieval, thereby implying higher degrees of abstraction (e.g., Chatterjee, ; Johnson, ; Tucker, ).…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%