1998
DOI: 10.2307/2585673
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Consequences of the Condorcet Jury Theorem for Beneficial Information Aggregation by Rational Agents

Abstract: “Naïve” Condorcet Jury Theorems automatically have “sophisticated” versions as corollaries. A Condorcet Jury Theorem is a result, pertaining to an election in which the agents have common preferences but diverse information, asserting that the outcome is better, on average, than the one that would be chosen by any particular individual. Sometimes there is the additional assertion that, as the population grows, the probability of an incorrect decision goes to zero. As a consequence of simple properties of commo… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1
1

Citation Types

1
121
0
1

Year Published

2001
2001
2011
2011

Publication Types

Select...
4
4
1

Relationship

0
9

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 213 publications
(123 citation statements)
references
References 18 publications
1
121
0
1
Order By: Relevance
“…Fortunately, our setting proposes a mechanism that results in the use of the 'first best' voting rule and is therefore immune to strategic non-informative voting. Such strategy-proofness does not hold under 'second best' anonymous aggregation rules, as have been demonstrated by Austen-Smith and Banks (1996), Ben-Yashar and Milchtaich (2007), Feddersen andPesendorfer (1998) andMcLennan (1998). In fact, in this setting, effective deliberation prior to the vote is expected to take place, as established in Coughlan (2000).…”
Section: T P a T P A T P T P A T P T P A T P A Tmentioning
confidence: 89%
“…Fortunately, our setting proposes a mechanism that results in the use of the 'first best' voting rule and is therefore immune to strategic non-informative voting. Such strategy-proofness does not hold under 'second best' anonymous aggregation rules, as have been demonstrated by Austen-Smith and Banks (1996), Ben-Yashar and Milchtaich (2007), Feddersen andPesendorfer (1998) andMcLennan (1998). In fact, in this setting, effective deliberation prior to the vote is expected to take place, as established in Coughlan (2000).…”
Section: T P a T P A T P T P A T P T P A T P A Tmentioning
confidence: 89%
“…This property is quite robust. For example, McLennan (1998) considers sequences of games with increasing n in which players have common preferences; full information equivalence again holds in the limit under very general conditions. Lohmann (1993) identifies conditions under which the same property holds when players demonstrate rather than vote.…”
Section: Related Literaturementioning
confidence: 99%
“…This paper shows that with unequal competences, one direction in this characterization holds for 2 Assuming commonality of preferences avoids confounding this kind of strategic voting with the kind that may result from the misalignment of different individuals' objectives. Strategic voting in the context of non-common preferences is studied, for example, in [12], [14], [15], [16], [17], [22], [23], [24], [26], [30] and [35]. For extensive strategic analysis of voting in committees, see [29].…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%