2020
DOI: 10.1093/restud/rdaa044
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Cognitive Imprecision and Small-Stakes Risk Aversion

Abstract: Observed choices between risky lotteries are difficult to reconcile with expected utility maximization, both because subjects appear to be too risk averse with regard to small gambles for this to be explained by diminishing marginal utility of wealth, as stressed by Rabin (2000), and because subjects’ responses involve a random element. We propose a unified explanation for both anomalies, similar to the explanation given for related phenomena in the case of perceptual judgments: they result from judgments base… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

12
128
0

Year Published

2021
2021
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
5
2
2

Relationship

2
7

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 108 publications
(140 citation statements)
references
References 88 publications
(203 reference statements)
12
128
0
Order By: Relevance
“…In Table 2 , the columns titled BIC calibration and BIC validation respectively report the average BIC values obtained from the calibration datasets and the remaining validation partitions. We follow Khaw, Li, and Woodford [ 29 ] in reporting a composite Bayes factor K = K 1 ⋅ K 2 , taking into account observations of both calibration and validation datasets. For any two models, and …”
Section: Resultsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…In Table 2 , the columns titled BIC calibration and BIC validation respectively report the average BIC values obtained from the calibration datasets and the remaining validation partitions. We follow Khaw, Li, and Woodford [ 29 ] in reporting a composite Bayes factor K = K 1 ⋅ K 2 , taking into account observations of both calibration and validation datasets. For any two models, and …”
Section: Resultsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…One important intuition is that some phenomena may be rational for an agent whose cognitive systems have finite precision, because they have limited numbers of neurons (Dasgupta & Gershman 2021;Franconeri et al 2013) or noisy inference (Drugowitsch et al 2016). For example, the concave mapping of monetary value to utility that is a ubiquitous property of econometric functions is adaptive if lower-valued goods are more frequently encountered than higher-valued goods (as seems plausible), even in the absence of any assumptions about risk preference (Khaw et al 2018). If valuation is conceived as a sampling process, and preferences are dynamically constructed by retrieving memories of past experiences to a current prospect, then utility and probability functions will be naturally tailored to match previously encountered distributions of value and probability.…”
Section: Rational Inattentionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…In combination with Bayesian decoding, a lognormal encoding scheme will ensure that utility functions exhibit the concavity that is characteristic of diminishing marginal utility, and that value estimates are contracted towards the prior mean (Khaw et al 2018). Of course the natural statistics of number, value, or quantity may be hard to measure, and so we must make some assumptions.…”
Section: Efficient Coding and Repulsive Choice Biasesmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…In Table 2, the columns titled BIC calibration and BIC validation respectively report the average BIC values obtained from the calibration datasets and the remaining validation partitions. We follow Khaw, Li, and Woodford [29] in reporting a composite Bayes factor K = K 1 � K 2 , taking into account observations of both calibration and validation datasets. For any two models, M 1 and…”
Section: Comparison To Second-best Specificationsmentioning
confidence: 99%