2017
DOI: 10.1016/j.eneco.2017.10.018
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Climate policies under climate model uncertainty: Max-min and min-max regret

Abstract: Standard-Nutzungsbedingungen:Die Dokumente auf EconStor dürfen zu eigenen wissenschaftlichen Zwecken und zum Privatgebrauch gespeichert und kopiert werden.Sie dürfen die Dokumente nicht für öffentliche oder kommerzielle Zwecke vervielfältigen, öffentlich ausstellen, öffentlich zugänglich machen, vertreiben oder anderweitig nutzen.Sofern die Verfasser die Dokumente unter Open-Content-Lizenzen (insbesondere CC-Lizenzen) zur Verfügung gestellt haben sollten, gelten abweichend von diesen Nutzungsbedingungen die in… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
4
0

Year Published

2017
2017
2022
2022

Publication Types

Select...
8

Relationship

3
5

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 15 publications
(6 citation statements)
references
References 36 publications
0
4
0
Order By: Relevance
“…† MMR has been applied in several policy areas, including criminal justice (6) and public health (7). It has been used in computational modeling of energy and climate policy in a number of studies (8)(9)(10)(11)(12). [Cai (13) reviews this research.]…”
Section: Significancementioning
confidence: 99%
“…† MMR has been applied in several policy areas, including criminal justice (6) and public health (7). It has been used in computational modeling of energy and climate policy in a number of studies (8)(9)(10)(11)(12). [Cai (13) reviews this research.]…”
Section: Significancementioning
confidence: 99%
“…As indicated earlier, the study of ambiguity in the context of climate policy is not without precedent, but discussions have generally been limited to cases when only the planner has doubts about the approximating climate-economic model. Such doubts include concerns about potential mis-specification of alternative models and ambiguity over how much weight to assign to each of these models, while agents themselves are usually assumed to have rational beliefs (see Millner et al (2012), Brock and Durlauf (2015), Cai et al (2013), Cai and Lontzek (2019), Anderson et al (2013), Berger et al (2016), Li et al (2016), Lemoine and Traeger (2016), Rezai and van der Ploeg (2017), and Barnett et al (2020)). Hennlock's (2009) is no exception in that, although he attributes deep uncertainty to the consumer, the government, being a direct extension of the consumer, remains the consumer's sole agent, so that, in effect, it is the planner who is modeled as having doubts about the model.…”
Section: Known Pessimistic Private Beliefs (A)mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…But climate sceptics might be persuaded to be in favour of curbing global warming, since the welfare cost of conducting climate policy when the climate deniers are right are modest (e.g., relatively small Harberger triangles as the revenue from carbon pricing is recycled) and the welfare cost of not conducting climate policy when the climate scientists are right are potentially very large (e.g., a third of GDP with unfettered global warming leading to 4 or 5 degrees Celsius). Rezai and van der Ploeg (2017b) show that maximising welfare under the worst possible outcome or minimising the regret of conducting the wrong policy both lead to an ambitious climate policy. If a model uncertainty approach with ambiguity aversion is used, policymakers still pursue an aggressive carbon pricing policy even if a probability that climate deniers are right of 10 or 20 per cent is used.…”
Section: Challenges and Obstacles To Successful Climate Policymentioning
confidence: 99%