2020
DOI: 10.37693/pjos.2019.9.21388
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Choice awareness and manipulation blindness: A cognitive semiotic exploration of choice-making

Abstract: Within cognitive science, “blindness” to choice is commonly treated as typical of human cognition, implying unreliable agents who essentially lack any awareness of their own choices (e.g. Johansson et al., 2005, 2008; Hall et al., 2010, 2013). Within cognitive semiotics, however, choice awareness is seen as a continuous phenomenon, which is susceptible to the influence of a variety of factors. Manipulation blindness  is proposed as a more adequate term for what is known in the literature as “choice blindness”,… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1

Citation Types

0
1
0

Year Published

2020
2020
2023
2023

Publication Types

Select...
5

Relationship

0
5

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 5 publications
(1 citation statement)
references
References 41 publications
0
1
0
Order By: Relevance
“…[T]he subject's sense of agency regarding her thoughts likewise depends on her belief that these mental episodes are expressions of her intentional states. That is, whether the subject regards an episode of thinking occurring in her psychological history as something she does, as her mental action, depends on whether she finds its occurrence explicable in terms of her theory or story of her own underlying intentional states (Graham & Stephens, 1994, p. 102, cited by Gallagher, 2012 As Gallagher and colleagues point out, this could indeed be the case sometimes, for example when participants in experiments use "folk psychological narratives" (Hutto, 2008) to make sense of their own actions, especially when these are manipulated, as in so-called "choice-blindness" studies, more properly referred to as (partial) manipulation blindness (Mouratidou, 2019). But these are very special cases, and they can hardly apply to the basic layers of operative agency (in our terms), or even to non-verbal reflections, such as evinced in non-human animals, as the stone caching and throwing chimpanzee Santino (see Section 2).…”
Section: A Cognitive-phenomenological Approach To Agencymentioning
confidence: 99%
“…[T]he subject's sense of agency regarding her thoughts likewise depends on her belief that these mental episodes are expressions of her intentional states. That is, whether the subject regards an episode of thinking occurring in her psychological history as something she does, as her mental action, depends on whether she finds its occurrence explicable in terms of her theory or story of her own underlying intentional states (Graham & Stephens, 1994, p. 102, cited by Gallagher, 2012 As Gallagher and colleagues point out, this could indeed be the case sometimes, for example when participants in experiments use "folk psychological narratives" (Hutto, 2008) to make sense of their own actions, especially when these are manipulated, as in so-called "choice-blindness" studies, more properly referred to as (partial) manipulation blindness (Mouratidou, 2019). But these are very special cases, and they can hardly apply to the basic layers of operative agency (in our terms), or even to non-verbal reflections, such as evinced in non-human animals, as the stone caching and throwing chimpanzee Santino (see Section 2).…”
Section: A Cognitive-phenomenological Approach To Agencymentioning
confidence: 99%