2015
DOI: 10.1007/s11098-015-0574-2
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Beliefs, buses and lotteries: Why rational belief can’t be stably high credence

Abstract: Until recently, it seemed like no theory about the relationship between rational credence and rational outright belief could reconcile three independently plausible assumptions: that our beliefs should be logically consistent, that our degrees of belief should be probabilistic, and that a rational agent believes something just in case she is sufficiently confident in it. Recently a new formal framework has been proposed that can accommodate these three assumptions, which is known as ''the stability theory of b… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
54
0

Year Published

2017
2017
2023
2023

Publication Types

Select...
8

Relationship

1
7

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 66 publications
(54 citation statements)
references
References 11 publications
0
54
0
Order By: Relevance
“…On a third view, the norms for each attitude are independent: maybe the norms for credence are probabilistic coherence and updating by conditionalization, and the norms for belief are deductive consistency (Frankish, 2009, p. 80; Weisberg, 2015). Relatedly, several authors have argued that rational belief and rational credence are sensitive to different features of a body of evidence, so, for example, one could rationally have a high credence in p, but should not believe p (see Buchak, 2014; Friedman, 2013; Jackson, 2019c, Forthcoming; Smith, 2010b, 2016; Staffel, 2015). We will return to fundamentality later, but now examine arguably the most widely‐discussed normative connection between belief and credence: the Lockean thesis.…”
Section: Belief and Credence: Normative Questionsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…On a third view, the norms for each attitude are independent: maybe the norms for credence are probabilistic coherence and updating by conditionalization, and the norms for belief are deductive consistency (Frankish, 2009, p. 80; Weisberg, 2015). Relatedly, several authors have argued that rational belief and rational credence are sensitive to different features of a body of evidence, so, for example, one could rationally have a high credence in p, but should not believe p (see Buchak, 2014; Friedman, 2013; Jackson, 2019c, Forthcoming; Smith, 2010b, 2016; Staffel, 2015). We will return to fundamentality later, but now examine arguably the most widely‐discussed normative connection between belief and credence: the Lockean thesis.…”
Section: Belief and Credence: Normative Questionsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…This is primarily due to considerations of space. For there is significant reason to think outright belief and credences, while related, are distinct and that their rational statuses may not systematically vary (Wedgwood 2012;Buchak 2013;Staffel 2016;cf. Weisberg forthcoming).…”
Section: Clarificationsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…The former requires rejecting (ST), while the latter requires rejecting (MPC). Proponents of the first strategy include Ryan (1996), Kaplan (1996), Nelkin (2000), Leplin (2009), Buchak (2014, Staffel (2016), and Smith (2010Smith ( , 2016. Proponents of the second strategy include Kyburg (1961), Foley (1992), David (2004, and Sturgeon (2008).…”
Section: The Lottery Paradoxmentioning
confidence: 99%