2019
DOI: 10.1080/13621025.2019.1700044
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Banishment and the pre-history of legitimate expulsion power

Abstract: In the introduction of a recent work on the denationalization of terrorists across the West, the legal scholar Audrey Macklin announced that "after decades in exile, banishment is back" (Macklin 2015). Over the last decade, as new laws allowing individuals to be stripped of citizenship have sprung up in states including the UK, Canada, Australia, Finland and the Netherlands, many others have also analogised denationalization to this medieval practice (Sassen 2015;Lenard 2019; Pillai & Williams 2017). By allowi… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1

Citation Types

0
9
0

Year Published

2020
2020
2023
2023

Publication Types

Select...
6

Relationship

0
6

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 9 publications
(9 citation statements)
references
References 32 publications
0
9
0
Order By: Relevance
“…Furthermore, such transferred, incomplete punishment initiated by (in many cases) developed Western states, exploits existing vulnerabilities of conflict-ridden states, and amplifies their dominated status. Gibney (2020) exposes the constraints of citizenship revocation in modern times caused by a lack of unoccupied territories, but this article nevertheless reveals the ways in which countries suffering from prolonged conflict which weakens their institutional framework and exposes them to non-state governance by militarized groups, effectively become the new terrae nullius for discarding undesirable citizens. Therefore, rather than depicting the appearance of global non-citizens as the inadvertent collateral consequence of enhanced global mobility, it is necessary to recognize the ways in which the (mostly) Western states consciously exploit existing pathways of dependencies of vulnerable states caused by their complex economic, political and institutional frailties.…”
Section: Who Punishes? Complete V Partial Punishmentmentioning
confidence: 97%
See 2 more Smart Citations
“…Furthermore, such transferred, incomplete punishment initiated by (in many cases) developed Western states, exploits existing vulnerabilities of conflict-ridden states, and amplifies their dominated status. Gibney (2020) exposes the constraints of citizenship revocation in modern times caused by a lack of unoccupied territories, but this article nevertheless reveals the ways in which countries suffering from prolonged conflict which weakens their institutional framework and exposes them to non-state governance by militarized groups, effectively become the new terrae nullius for discarding undesirable citizens. Therefore, rather than depicting the appearance of global non-citizens as the inadvertent collateral consequence of enhanced global mobility, it is necessary to recognize the ways in which the (mostly) Western states consciously exploit existing pathways of dependencies of vulnerable states caused by their complex economic, political and institutional frailties.…”
Section: Who Punishes? Complete V Partial Punishmentmentioning
confidence: 97%
“…Denationalization, therefore, is ideally conceived as a two-step process of disowning citizens and transferring them to a country of their 'residual' (Bolhuis and van Wijk 2020) citizenship (Macklin 2015;Mantu 2015;Esbrook 2016;Gibney 2020). While the process centres on transferring a person, it also importantly allocates control and responsibility over the person: 'deportees are… returned or repatriated to their country of membership rather than banished or exiled' (Gibney 2020: 296, emphasis in the original).…”
Section: Citizenship Revocation As Transferal Of Responsibility To An...mentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…And while the modus operandi of current-day denationalisation is partially distinct from its predecessor modes, 4 recent contestations of both a legal, normative and historical nature suggest that contemporary citizenship revocation have not truly shaken off its discriminatory past. 5 Matthew Gibney (2019) has pointed to citizenship revocation laws in the U.K. as an example of how some denationalisation provisions continue to have discriminatory effects. 6 While underlying motives may vary from case to case, discrimination is often at the heart of the matter, when states strip citizens of their status and for this reason alone, the rise of denationalisation across Western liberal societies calls for scepticism.…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Contemporary denationalisation operates in a different context than its historical predecessors and must navigate international obligations including the prohibition on the creation of statelessness. 69 Yet, 'doctrinal approvals' and the gradual acceptance of denationalisation laws that target dual citizens are in constant risk of 'human rights-washing' a practice that otherwise, by most normative accounts, is considered destructive to liberal society by propagating the misconception that denationalisation in the 21st century has somehow become morally 'right'. There is, in essence, nothing egalitarian about indirectly protecting the citizenship of a 'puritan' majority of citizens, while enabling the deprivation of citizenship from dual citizens who are often of another ethnicity, race, national origin or religion.…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%