2006
DOI: 10.7861/clinmedicine.6-4-374
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Assisted dying: a palliative care physician’s view

Abstract: , but it may return to Parliament in Autumn 2006. Assisted dying is being promoted as a logical extension to patient autonomy for those who are terminally ill and suffering intolerably, and proponents claim to have overwhelming public support. Those who have most experience of caring for the terminally ill, however, come out most strongly against any change in the current law. This paper suggests that estimates of public opinion are unreliable; that assisted dying is unnecessary if we are prepared to prioritis… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
2
1

Citation Types

0
6
0

Year Published

2014
2014
2023
2023

Publication Types

Select...
5

Relationship

0
5

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 6 publications
(6 citation statements)
references
References 1 publication
0
6
0
Order By: Relevance
“…Several recent publications take the latter position, specifically challenging the Belgian construct of "integral palliative care" and arguing that physician-assisted dying and palliative care are fundamentally antagonistic causes (Jaspers, Müller-Busch & Nauck, 2009;Kettler & Nauck, 2010;Johnstone, 2012;Materstvedt, 2012). The principled rejection of "integral palliative care" is in line with traditional views in mainstream palliative care (Roy &Rapin, 1994;Hamel, 1998;Mast, Salama, Silverman, & Arnold, 2004;Meisel, 2005;Stephenson, 2006;Bosshard, Broeckaert,Clark, Materstvedt, Gordijn& Müller-Busch, 2008). Indeed, the prevention of physician-assisted dying was one of the prime motivations of the founders of the palliative care movement (Saunders, 1976) and this tenet has remained widely endorsed ever since (Gordijn& Janssens, 2000;…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 77%
“…Several recent publications take the latter position, specifically challenging the Belgian construct of "integral palliative care" and arguing that physician-assisted dying and palliative care are fundamentally antagonistic causes (Jaspers, Müller-Busch & Nauck, 2009;Kettler & Nauck, 2010;Johnstone, 2012;Materstvedt, 2012). The principled rejection of "integral palliative care" is in line with traditional views in mainstream palliative care (Roy &Rapin, 1994;Hamel, 1998;Mast, Salama, Silverman, & Arnold, 2004;Meisel, 2005;Stephenson, 2006;Bosshard, Broeckaert,Clark, Materstvedt, Gordijn& Müller-Busch, 2008). Indeed, the prevention of physician-assisted dying was one of the prime motivations of the founders of the palliative care movement (Saunders, 1976) and this tenet has remained widely endorsed ever since (Gordijn& Janssens, 2000;…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 77%
“…[39][40][41] Ethical discourse on EAS is also concerned with the risk of harming the vulnerable, which is one of the most frequently cited reasons for opposing EAS legalisation. 20,21 Authors usually define the vulnerable by portraying concrete groups with one or more typical features, such as young or old age, impaired cognitive capacity, lower social status and similar. The American College of Physicians defined the vulnerable as the sick, the elderly, children, the disabled, the poor and members of minority groups and expressed worries about subtle biases and adverse judgements on the worth of their lives, which legalisation of EAS could bring.…”
Section: A Need For Protection Of the Vulnerable In Eas Practicesmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…I believe that this [EAS] is such a case'. 20 Despite disagreement about whether limitation of one's autonomy is justified in the case of EAS, a sensitive and respectful approach that avoids blindly 'labelling' certain people as vulnerable is crucial. 13 The most autonomous as the most existentially vulnerable…”
Section: Danger Of Discrimination Against Those Proclaimed As Vulnerablementioning
confidence: 99%
See 2 more Smart Citations