2018
DOI: 10.1016/j.artint.2018.07.006
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Approximating optimal social choice under metric preferences

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1

Citation Types

9
324
5

Year Published

2018
2018
2021
2021

Publication Types

Select...
5
1

Relationship

2
4

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 106 publications
(338 citation statements)
references
References 24 publications
9
324
5
Order By: Relevance
“…From Figure 1 and 2, we can see that the distortion is minimized when τ = 1 + √ 2 in both settings. With only voter preferences being known, the best known deterministic distortion bounds are 3 for two candidates [1], and 4.236 for multiple candidates [25]. Interestingly, if we are also allowed to a choose a threshold τ , our results indicate that the optimal thing to do is to differentiate between candidates with lots of supporters who prefer them at least 1 + √ 2 times to other candidates, and candidates which have few such supporters.…”
Section: Distortionmentioning
confidence: 85%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…From Figure 1 and 2, we can see that the distortion is minimized when τ = 1 + √ 2 in both settings. With only voter preferences being known, the best known deterministic distortion bounds are 3 for two candidates [1], and 4.236 for multiple candidates [25]. Interestingly, if we are also allowed to a choose a threshold τ , our results indicate that the optimal thing to do is to differentiate between candidates with lots of supporters who prefer them at least 1 + √ 2 times to other candidates, and candidates which have few such supporters.…”
Section: Distortionmentioning
confidence: 85%
“…Many insights were obtained for this setting, including that there are deterministic voting rules which obtain a distortion of at most a small constant (5 in [1], and more recently 4.236 in [25]), and that no deterministic rule can obtain a distortion of better than 3 given access to only ordinal information. 1 The fundamental assumption and motivation in the above work is that the strength or intensity of voter preferences is not possible to obtain, and thus we must do the best we can with only ordinal preferences. And indeed, knowing the exact strength of voter preferences is usually impossible.…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…In particular, Anshelevich et al (2015) study the same setting as Boutilier et al (2015), but in addition assume the preferences of voters are consistent with distances in a metric space. Approximating utilitarian social welfare given ordinal information has also been studied in mechanism design.…”
Section: Related Workmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…In addition to the aforementioned papers (Procaccia & Rosenschein, 2006;Boutilier et al, 2015), several other papers employ the notion of distortion to quantify how close one can get to maximizing utilitarian social welfare when only ordinal preferences are available (Caragiannis & Procaccia, 2011;Anshelevich, Bhardwaj, & Postl, 2015;Anshelevich & Postl, 2016;Anshelevich & Sekar, 2016). In particular, Anshelevich et al (2015) study the same setting as Boutilier et al (2015), but in addition assume the preferences of voters are consistent with distances in a metric space.…”
Section: Related Workmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…However, this is not anymore the case if one uses the maximal lotteries randomised voting rule (Brandl et al, 2016). 2 (viii) Better welfare guarantees When considering cardinal preferences over outcomes, a probabilistic approach may achieve better approximation welfare guarantees while simultaneously achieving other axiomatic properties (Anshelevich et al, 2015;Anshelevich and Postl, 2016;Procaccia, 2010).…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%