1998
DOI: 10.1075/pbns.58.12noh
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

A Relevance-theoretic Account of Metarepresentative Uses in Conditionals

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
12
0

Year Published

2006
2006
2020
2020

Publication Types

Select...
6
1
1

Relationship

1
7

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 14 publications
(13 citation statements)
references
References 25 publications
0
12
0
Order By: Relevance
“…Here are some possible examples: In (37a), the vicar metarepresents an utterance that he wants the bride to produce. In the "speech-act conditional" in (38), the consequent is used to metarepresent an utterance that Mary wants Peter to produce; (38) expresses something like the proposition "If that's John, say I'm not here" (Sweetser 1990;Noh 1998b;van der Auwera 1986). The quiz-show question in (39) might be analysed on similar lines: the host is not producing a regular interrogative, but metarepresenting an utterance he wants the contestant to produce.…”
Section: Non-attributive Casesmentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…Here are some possible examples: In (37a), the vicar metarepresents an utterance that he wants the bride to produce. In the "speech-act conditional" in (38), the consequent is used to metarepresent an utterance that Mary wants Peter to produce; (38) expresses something like the proposition "If that's John, say I'm not here" (Sweetser 1990;Noh 1998b;van der Auwera 1986). The quiz-show question in (39) might be analysed on similar lines: the host is not producing a regular interrogative, but metarepresenting an utterance he wants the contestant to produce.…”
Section: Non-attributive Casesmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…In (18a), the causal relation is between two states of affairs; in (18b), it is between a state of affairs and an utterance or thought. In interpreting (18b), the hearer must construct a higher-order representation of the type "she says", or "she thinks", and attribute it as part of the speaker's meaning (Noh 1998b;Papafragou 1998aPapafragou , 1998bSweetser 1990; for developmental studies, see Noveck, Ho & Sera 1996;Papafragou 1998c). In (18b), the inferred higher-order representation may be either epistemic or illocutionary.…”
Section: Decoding and Inference In Linguistic Metarepresentationmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Conditionals, on the other hand, are more complex since they consist of two clauses: an antecedent and a consequent of various semantic types. Noh (1996) analyses conditionals from a relevance-theoretic view, arguing that in many cases antecedents are used interpretively to represent a contextually given proposition. The next sub-sections elaborate on each of the three structures.…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…If we consider that the proposition expressed in the antecedent is a proposition that the reader is probably 'thinking about' at the time of processing the visual stimulus, then its relation to the imperative becomes more plausible. Noh (1996) discusses given antecedents in conditionals as a case of metarepresentative use. In terms of relevance theory, she analyses them as a case of interpretive use since "given antecedents are used to represent another representation in context" (1996: 15).…”
Section: Conditionalsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…(b) Smith and Smith (1988), Foster-Cohen (1997) and Noh (1996) have applied RT to conditionals. In general, there is some discussion on whether conditionals are similar to the logical "implication" or closer to non-truth-functional words relating the antecedent and the consequent in the sentence.…”
Section: Studies On Grammar From a Relevance-theoretic Perspectivementioning
confidence: 99%