2011
DOI: 10.1007/s00355-011-0565-y
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

A measure of distance between judgment sets

Abstract: In the literature on judgment aggregation, an important open question is how to measure the distance between any two judgment sets. This is relevant for issues of social choice: if two individuals hold different beliefs then we might want to find a compromise that lies somewhere between them. We propose a set of axioms that determine a measure of distance uniquely. This measure differs from the widely used Hamming metric. The difference between Hamming's metric and ours boils down to one axiom. Given judgment … Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1

Citation Types

0
30
0
2

Year Published

2011
2011
2016
2016

Publication Types

Select...
4
3

Relationship

1
6

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 27 publications
(32 citation statements)
references
References 14 publications
0
30
0
2
Order By: Relevance
“…There is a large literature on alternative distance measures between preferences, for example [5,13,21,22,24,31,36]. It has been argued in for example [34,12], that the Hamming distance as a measure of dissimilarity may not be appropriate when the elements in the preference set are logically related. For example, A ≡ B and B ≡ A are logically related (logically equivalent in fact).…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…There is a large literature on alternative distance measures between preferences, for example [5,13,21,22,24,31,36]. It has been argued in for example [34,12], that the Hamming distance as a measure of dissimilarity may not be appropriate when the elements in the preference set are logically related. For example, A ≡ B and B ≡ A are logically related (logically equivalent in fact).…”
Section: Discussionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…The recent conference 'Judgment aggregation and voting' in Freudenstadt in 2011 however marks a visible shift of attention towards constructing concrete aggregation rules and finding 'second best' solutions in the face of impossibility results. The new proposals range from a first Borda-type aggregation rule (Zwicker 2011) to, among others, new distance-based rules (Duddy and Piggins 2012) and rules which approximate the majority judgments when these are inconsistent (Nehring et al 2011). The more traditional proposals include premise-and conclusion-based rules (e.g., Kornhauser and Sager 1986;Pettit 2001;List and Pettit 2002;Dietrich 2006a;Dietrich and Mongin 2010), sequential rules (e.g., List 2004;Dietrich and List 2007b), distance-based rules (e.g., Konieczny and Pino-Perez 2002;Pigozzi 2006;Miller and Osherson 2008;Eckert and Klamler 2009;Hartmann et al 2010;Lang et al 2011), and quota rules with well-calibrated acceptance thresholds and various degrees of collective rationality (e.g., Dietrich and List 2007b; see also Nehring and Puppe 2010a).…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Thus, the Hamming distance is the same between, say, a judgment that the value of a certain parameter is 1 and the judgment that this value is 0 as between the judgments that this value is 1 and .9, respectively. Another kind of criticism has been levelled by Duddy & Piggins (2012), who argue that the Hamming metric will sometimes involve double-counting if the propositions on the agenda are allowed to be logically interconnected. To use their example, if two individuals both accept a proposition p, then they disagree on the conjunction p  q iff they disagree on q.…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…In view of the relationship between the Hamming metric and the KS-measure, this objection might have implications for the use of the latter measure as well. And indeed, Duddy and Piggins (2012) argue that it does. For their own proposal of a measure of distance between rankings, see Appendix.…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation