1980
DOI: 10.3758/bf03213778
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

The belief-bias effect in formal reasoning: The influence of knowledge on logic

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1
1

Citation Types

3
40
0
2

Year Published

1989
1989
2010
2010

Publication Types

Select...
7
2

Relationship

0
9

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 153 publications
(45 citation statements)
references
References 25 publications
3
40
0
2
Order By: Relevance
“…The belief-bias effect refers to the tendency to accept a conclusion that accords with one's belief, regardless of whether that conclusion is in fact valid. This effect has been widely replicated (e.g., Cherubini et al, 1998;Evans et al, 1983;Evans, Newstead, Allen, & Pollard, 1994;Evans & Pollard, 1990;Feather, 1964;Janis & Frick, 1943;Markovits & BouffardBouchard, 1992;Markovits & Nantel, 1989;Morgan & Morton, 1944;Newstead et al, 1992;Oakhill & Johnson-Laird, 1985;Oakhill, Johnson-Laird & Garnham, 1989;Revlin et al, 1980;Stanovich & West, 1997;Thompson, 1996;Torrens, Thompson, & Cramer, 1999). In contrast to the rather pessimistic view of human rationality suggested by the belief-bias effect, however, it has also been widely observed that reasoners accept more valid than invalid conclusions, regardless of believability (Evans et al, 1983;Evans et al, 1994;Newstead et al, 1992;Thompson, 1994Thompson, , 1996Torrens et al, 1999).…”
Section: Beliefs and Validity In Deductive Reasoningmentioning
confidence: 71%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…The belief-bias effect refers to the tendency to accept a conclusion that accords with one's belief, regardless of whether that conclusion is in fact valid. This effect has been widely replicated (e.g., Cherubini et al, 1998;Evans et al, 1983;Evans, Newstead, Allen, & Pollard, 1994;Evans & Pollard, 1990;Feather, 1964;Janis & Frick, 1943;Markovits & BouffardBouchard, 1992;Markovits & Nantel, 1989;Morgan & Morton, 1944;Newstead et al, 1992;Oakhill & Johnson-Laird, 1985;Oakhill, Johnson-Laird & Garnham, 1989;Revlin et al, 1980;Stanovich & West, 1997;Thompson, 1996;Torrens, Thompson, & Cramer, 1999). In contrast to the rather pessimistic view of human rationality suggested by the belief-bias effect, however, it has also been widely observed that reasoners accept more valid than invalid conclusions, regardless of believability (Evans et al, 1983;Evans et al, 1994;Newstead et al, 1992;Thompson, 1994Thompson, , 1996Torrens et al, 1999).…”
Section: Beliefs and Validity In Deductive Reasoningmentioning
confidence: 71%
“…As mentioned earlier, the default method is a within-subjects design whereby reasoners are asked to complete a large number of very similar reasoning problems. A quick review of several recent belief-bias studies (Cherubini et al, 1998;Evans et al, 1983;Evans et al, 1994;Evans & Pollard, 1990;Markovits & BouffardBouchard, 1992;Markovits & Nantel, 1989;Newstead et al, 1992;Oakhill & JohnsonLaird, 1985;Oakhill et al, 1989;Revlin et al, 1980;Stanovich & West, 1997;Thompson, 1996;Torrens et al, 1999) indicated that the median number of problems reasoners are asked to solve is 8 (mean=9) ; typically, reasoners are asked to solve some multiple of four (allowing one problem in each belief by validity cell) or six problems (when a neutral belief condition is included).…”
Section: The Relative Merits Of Within-and Between-subjects Designsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Sixteen syllogistic problem frames were used (see Appendix D): Eight problem frames controlled for atmosphere (Begg & Denny, 1969), conversion (Dickstein, 1975(Dickstein, , 1981Revlin, Leirer, Yopp, & Yopp, 1980), and figural effects (Dickstein, 1978), and eight controlled for atmosphere and figure, but not conversion. Although the design of this experiment did not require control of these structural effects, this decision allowed use of exactly the same problem frames in Experiments 2 and 3, where conclusion believability was manipulated.…”
Section: Methodsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Specifically, subjects will tend to rate an argument as valid if they think that the conclusion is empirically true, and vice versa, irrespective of the textbook validity of the argument. The reality of the belief-bias effect has been questioned (Revlin & Leirer, 1978;Revlin, Leirer, Yopp, & Yopp, 1980), mainly on the grounds that some of the effects observed may be attributable to conversion effects due to subjects' idiosyncratic encoding of premises. However, Evans, Barston, and Pollard (1983) have demonstrated a strong belief-bias effect in experiments designed to control for both conversion and atmosphere effects.…”
Section: Henry Markovits and Guilaine Nantelmentioning
confidence: 99%