2011
DOI: 10.1007/s10828-011-9043-2
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

On the syntactically complex status of negative indefinites

Abstract: Negative Indefinites (NIs) in languages such as Dutch and German may give rise to split-scope readings. Sentences like German Du must keine Krawatte anziehen ('you must wear no tie') have a reading where the modal takes scope in between the negation and the indefinite. In this paper I argue that West Germanic NIs are not negative quantifiers (in the Montegovian sense), but complex syntactic structures that consist of an abstract negative operator and an indefinite that are spelled out as a single word. Split-s… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
2
1
1

Citation Types

2
36
0

Year Published

2013
2013
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
6
1

Relationship

1
6

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 51 publications
(50 citation statements)
references
References 19 publications
(21 reference statements)
2
36
0
Order By: Relevance
“…Account 1 extended Zeijlstra's (2004) Agree theory of negative concord to apply to all three variants such that (i) not-negation contains a negative marker in NegP with [ineg]; (ii) no-negation arises due to Agree between a covert negative operator in NegP that has [ineg] and a post-verbal indefinite DP with [uneg]; and (iii) negative concord is the result of Agree between the negative marker with [ineg] and indefinite DPs with [uneg]. Under Account 2, not-negation and negative concord are derived in the same way as in Account 1, but no-negation is instead the result of negative-marking within the DP which subsequently moves to the higher NegP for sentential scope (based on Kayne 1998;Svenonius 2002;Zeijlstra 2011).…”
Section: Resultsmentioning
confidence: 99%
See 3 more Smart Citations
“…Account 1 extended Zeijlstra's (2004) Agree theory of negative concord to apply to all three variants such that (i) not-negation contains a negative marker in NegP with [ineg]; (ii) no-negation arises due to Agree between a covert negative operator in NegP that has [ineg] and a post-verbal indefinite DP with [uneg]; and (iii) negative concord is the result of Agree between the negative marker with [ineg] and indefinite DPs with [uneg]. Under Account 2, not-negation and negative concord are derived in the same way as in Account 1, but no-negation is instead the result of negative-marking within the DP which subsequently moves to the higher NegP for sentential scope (based on Kayne 1998;Svenonius 2002;Zeijlstra 2011).…”
Section: Resultsmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Haegeman 1995;Watanabe 2004;Wallage 2017: 185) or composed of a negative operator plus an indefinite (e.g. Zeijlstra 2011;Penka 2012;Tubau 2016). Either of these DP structures are tenable for Account 2 and this does not matter for the purposes of my analysis (see Iatridou and Sichel 2011: 610-12), as the crucial property of no-negation in this account is that negation is marked syntactically within the DP.…”
Section: Accountmentioning
confidence: 92%
See 2 more Smart Citations
“…Within the so-called decompositional approach it is said that split-scope effects result from lexical decomposition of the negative indefinite into a separate negation and an existential. Scholars differ whether this decomposition is the result of amalgamation (Jacobs 1980), incorporation (Rullmann 1995), syntactic agreement (Penka 2010) or a post-syntactic spell-out rule (Zeijlstra 2011).…”
Section: Negated Indefinitesmentioning
confidence: 99%