2017
DOI: 10.48550/arxiv.1703.00056
|View full text |Cite
Preprint
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Fair prediction with disparate impact: A study of bias in recidivism prediction instruments

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
3
1
1

Citation Types

2
70
0

Year Published

2018
2018
2022
2022

Publication Types

Select...
5
2
1

Relationship

0
8

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 31 publications
(72 citation statements)
references
References 0 publications
2
70
0
Order By: Relevance
“…Proof: The proof of this result is almost identical to the proof of the previous lemma with the only changes that • = • 2 and that we stop after applying (23) to (21).…”
Section: B Slowly Varying Unknown Noise Covariancementioning
confidence: 67%
“…Proof: The proof of this result is almost identical to the proof of the previous lemma with the only changes that • = • 2 and that we stop after applying (23) to (21).…”
Section: B Slowly Varying Unknown Noise Covariancementioning
confidence: 67%
“…Three of them have been considered both in the literature and in the popular press: equalizing false positive rates, false negative rates, and positive predictive value. These three notions of fairness are of particular interest to us because it has been shown that attaining all three measures simultaneously is impossible (Kleinberg et al [2016], Chouldechova [2017]). Given a policy β g for group g, true positive rate (TPR), false positive rate (FPR), false negative rate (FNR), and positive predictive value (PPV) are defined as…”
Section: Fairness Measuresmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…ProPublica argued that the algorithm's predictions did not maintain parity in false positive and false negative rates between white and black defendants, 1 while Northpointe countered that their algorithm satisfied predictive parity. 2 Subsequent research identified hard trade-offs in the choice of fairness metrics: under some mild conditions, the two requirements above cannot simultaneously be satisfied (Kleinberg et al [2016], Chouldechova [2017]). This inspired a literature proposing (or criticizing) notions of fairness based on ethical/ normative grounds.…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation
“…Numerous mathematical definitions of fairness have been proposed; examples include demographic parity [Dwork et al, 2012], disparate impact [Zafar et al, 2017], equality of odds [Hardt et al, 2016;Feldman et al, 2015], and calibration [Kleinberg et al, 2017]. While each of these notions is appealing on its own, it has been shown that they are incompatible with one another and cannot hold simultaneously [Kleinberg et al, 2017;Chouldechova, 2017]. The literature so far has dealt with these impossibility results by attempting to quantify the tradeoffs between different formulations of fairness, hoping that practitioners will be better positioned to determine the extent to which the violation of each fairness criterion can be socially tolerated (see, e.g., [Corbett-Davies et al, 2017]).…”
Section: Introductionmentioning
confidence: 99%