2003
DOI: 10.1017/s0034412503006589
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

Evil and the complexity of history: a response to Durston

Abstract: Kirk Durston recently presented an argument aimed against evidential arguments from evil predicated on instances of suffering that appear to be gratuitous; ‘The consequential complexity of history and gratuitous evil’, Religious Studies, 36 (2000), 65–80. He begins with the notion that history consists of an intricate web of causal chains, so that a single event in one such chain may have countless unforeseen consequences. According to Durston, this consequential complexity exhibited by history negatively impa… Show more

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
3
0

Year Published

2006
2006
2015
2015

Publication Types

Select...
4

Relationship

1
3

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 4 publications
(3 citation statements)
references
References 2 publications
(1 reference statement)
0
3
0
Order By: Relevance
“…If all we know is that (A soc − B soc ) is negative, we are in no position at all to infer the intrinsic moral value (E soc ) of the society at the time it was destroyed or decimated; it may actually have been positive. Nick Trakakis has pointed out that the consequential complexity of history also prevents us from knowing if a primary event that has a positive intrinsic value leads to a gratuitous evil (Trakakis (2003), 451). To clarify, for a single event, its intrinsic moral value (E) may actually be positive but the consequences that unfold from that event, when compared to the best alternative, may result in a negative (A − B).…”
Section: Problem Three: Were Destroyed Societies Evil?mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…If all we know is that (A soc − B soc ) is negative, we are in no position at all to infer the intrinsic moral value (E soc ) of the society at the time it was destroyed or decimated; it may actually have been positive. Nick Trakakis has pointed out that the consequential complexity of history also prevents us from knowing if a primary event that has a positive intrinsic value leads to a gratuitous evil (Trakakis (2003), 451). To clarify, for a single event, its intrinsic moral value (E) may actually be positive but the consequences that unfold from that event, when compared to the best alternative, may result in a negative (A − B).…”
Section: Problem Three: Were Destroyed Societies Evil?mentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Not all philosophers are convinced that the moral judgments made in the arguments for atheism are this complex (e.g. Trakakis 2003, 2006), but given the pro tanto case presented in examples like the foregoing, the burden of proof lies with the critic.…”
Section: The Case For Skeptical Theismmentioning
confidence: 99%
“…Without a doubt, the most serious and widespread criticism of skeptical theism is that it is somehow at odds with either moral deliberation (Fales 1992; Russell 1996; Almeida and Oppy 2003, 2004; Hasker 2004; Pereboom 2004, 2005; Piper 2007; Maitzen 2009) or moral knowledge (Wachterhauser 1985; Russell 1996; Trakakis 2003; Jordan 2006; Schnall 2007). If we are never in a position to tell whether God has a reason for allowing a particular prima facie evil or not, then we are never in a position to tell whether we should allow a particular prima facie evil or not.…”
Section: 8 Inconsistent With Moral Deliberation/moral Knowledgementioning
confidence: 99%