2019
DOI: 10.1017/9781108566216
|View full text |Cite
|
Sign up to set email alerts
|

A Theory of Legal Obligation

Help me understand this report

Search citation statements

Order By: Relevance

Paper Sections

Select...
1
1
1

Citation Types

0
4
0
1

Year Published

2020
2020
2024
2024

Publication Types

Select...
6
2

Relationship

0
8

Authors

Journals

citations
Cited by 12 publications
(5 citation statements)
references
References 193 publications
0
4
0
1
Order By: Relevance
“…From a normative perspective, they suggest that the values articulated in that part of the Treaty 'should inform policy-makers about the outer boundaries of policy formulation and implementation', since 'even if actors cooperate sincerely and respect the limits of their proper competences this does not automatically result in coherent policy outcomes'. 30 Bertea's observation that 'what is coherent forms a rational unit rather than a chaotic assemblage of possibly inconsistent normative statements' resonates here too; 31 though it should be remembered that chaos can stem from 'contradictions and overlapping'. 32 Thus while the idea of using Articles 2 and 3 TEU to cut through ambiguity regarding the values that should guide Union action, the problem is that those provisions themselves express attachment to so many values as to render any formal sense of instruction that they could provide ultimately futile.…”
Section: A Legal Charactermentioning
confidence: 86%
“…From a normative perspective, they suggest that the values articulated in that part of the Treaty 'should inform policy-makers about the outer boundaries of policy formulation and implementation', since 'even if actors cooperate sincerely and respect the limits of their proper competences this does not automatically result in coherent policy outcomes'. 30 Bertea's observation that 'what is coherent forms a rational unit rather than a chaotic assemblage of possibly inconsistent normative statements' resonates here too; 31 though it should be remembered that chaos can stem from 'contradictions and overlapping'. 32 Thus while the idea of using Articles 2 and 3 TEU to cut through ambiguity regarding the values that should guide Union action, the problem is that those provisions themselves express attachment to so many values as to render any formal sense of instruction that they could provide ultimately futile.…”
Section: A Legal Charactermentioning
confidence: 86%
“…1 Recientes contribuciones sobre la obligatoriedad del derecho, incluye la obra de Stefano Bertea (Bertea, 2019). Nótese que mi rechazo a la idea de inferir un concepto de obligatoriedad a partir de la teoría de la acción de Anscombe y de la razón práctica tiene su raíz Comparto con Scavuzzo la idea de que la práctica social es fundamental para comprender el punto de vista interno, o más bien, lo que yo llamo el punto de vista de quien delibera o el de la primera persona.…”
Section: Respuestas a Las Críticas Formuladas Por Natalia Scavuzzounclassified
“…Therefore, including or excluding an 'item' in the abductive 66 From this point of view, all analytical and procedural theories of legal justification and/or reasoning which are based on hierarchical as well as systemic/functional semantics seem to me unable to immunize themselves from the cognitive transmuting inherent in all the descriptive categories that legal language needs to involve in its statements. For an interesting and critical overview of the huge literature on this topic see [5,6]; with specific regard to the analytical legal approach, see above. I would like to emphasize that the cognitive motility tied to the descriptive parts of legal statements assumes crucial relevance when legal cases involve cultural differences.…”
Section: How the Limits To The 'Limits Of Law' Make Legal Semantic Resources Mobilementioning
confidence: 99%
“…Consider, thus, the following passages of Greimas' essay titled, 'Semiotic Analysis of a Legal Discourse. The Trade Act on Corporations and Company Groups' (1976) 6 :…”
mentioning
confidence: 99%
See 1 more Smart Citation